Global Goals: For What?

[with Ingrid Kvangraven (ingridhk@gmail.com); The New School for Social Research, New York: published in a slightly different version today on the FT online]

Should we really have new global development goals? The push for Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs) — meant to guide the process of global development from 2015 to 2030 and expected to be adopted by governments at the UN in September —assumes the answer. Activists, lobbyists and government officials scrambled during the last two years to make sure that their respective interests were reflected in the new agenda and that has contributed to its bewildering complexity (17 goals, 169 proposed targets and 304 proposed indicators). Given the goals were all but sure to be adopted it is hardly a surprise that an imperfect political process governed their creation.  However, why adopt goals at all? Any systematic effort to answer this elementary conceptual question is disturbingly absent.

Not only has this basic question has not been answered. What is most puzzling is that it has hardly been asked, both about the previous goals and the incoming ones. The public has instead been treated to a refrain from the global development bureaucracy that the outgoing Millennium Development Goals (MDGs) were a huge success, and that therefore we must proceed with a new round.

Secretary General Ban Ki-Moon recently claimed that the “…MDGs helped to lift more than one billion people out of extreme poverty.” Unfortunately, there is little justification for this statement. Whether the MDGs helped to advance development should ultimately be assessed in light of what would have happened without them. However, UN statistician Howard Friedman finds no statistically significant accelerations of global progress in the MDG indicators after the goals were introduced in 2000, except for on debt relief.

Although poverty has fallen since 2000 according to the most widely used estimates, the global rate of poverty reduction has not increased, and similarly with other indicators.  To argue that the goals contributed to poverty reduction, their defenders have to point to specific regions such as Sub-Saharan Africa—but here, other factors such as robust economic growth due in large part to the global commodities boom after 2000 and before the recent slowdown probably played a much more important causal role.

Why then the presumption that the MDGs were a success and that successor goals must be adopted? There are several possible reasons for this drumbeat. One is the bureaucratic propensity to self-justification. Another is that the language of accountability through quantifiable targets, initially pushed by aid donors, has gained widespread currency, perhaps because insiders understand how little it means in practice: given the number and complexity of the causes for observed outcomes, responsibility for shortfalls is nearly impossible to assign.

What are the good reasons to adopt goals of any kind? We may imagine three, all of which might be present in global development—although this must be argued rather than assumed. First, goals can have an epistemic role: they provide a framework for organizing information by fixing a reference point in relation to which achievements and shortfalls can be defined and compared. Second, goals can play a motivational role: a goal viewed as desirable may spur to individual and collective efforts either because of the psychology of intrinsic motivation or because they become the object of external incentives. Third, goals can provide a focal point around which actors coordinate their actions, which in the case of interdependencies between different actors (for instance, aid donors) may lead to better outcomes than otherwise.

If global development goals create a benefit by playing these roles, this has to be compared with their cost: for instance, by leading to people and institutions focusing relentless on goal monitoring and related tasks or otherwise crowding out more open-ended or process-centered understandings of what development is about and how it is to be achieved.

Aside from questions of justification, there are questions of specification. In any goal-setting exercise, there must be consistency between end-goals and intermediate goals as well as between means and ends. For example, if your end-goal were to be able to do one hundred push-ups by the beginning of November, it would very likely be insufficiently ambitious to set an intermediate goal of being able to do only ten pushups by the middle of October. Are the targets identified in the global goals merely intermediate goals, and if so toward what? Whether they are too ambitious or insufficiently so must be judged in light of considerations both of realism and of ultimate goals. Are you doing pushups to improve your health, to prepare for a competition, to test yourself, or to win friends? Knowing this will help evaluate whether the goals (and more subsidiary targets) that you are setting make sense. There may be better ways to gain friends than to do pushups, for instance.  Whether the time spent on doing pushups is desirable will also have to be assessed in light of the other uses of your time, your various goals and the extent to which push-ups would contribute to or detract from those as well. (In the development context, trade-offs and interdependencies between the quantity and pattern of growth and environmental quality may need to be considered for instance).

In addition to the opportunity cost of deploying resources in one way rather than another one must also ask whether, even if particular goals sometimes draw attention to neglected worthy aims or tasks that they highlight, the focus on the identified goals can also lead to inattention to others that have not been recognized.  No list can ever be comprehensive, and the more that it is the weaker its claim to drawing attention to specific aims.

The question of what development goals to adopt is inseparable, both in terms of instrumentality and values, from the question of what kind of world we ultimately wish to create. In practice, a paradox of specification must be faced: On the one hand, highly abstract but agreeable goals such as to ‘improve one’s health’ may lack sufficient directive implication. In contrast, highly specific goals such as to ‘eat spinach at least twice a week’ may be too directive, failing to recognize other means of attaining ultimate aims, offering insufficient room for variation across situations, paying too little heed to the way in which the attainment of aims results progressively and in difficult-to-anticipate ways from a sequence of specific steps that build on one another, and not recognizing the impact of actions aiming to promote one goal on the ability to attain others.

Focusing on eliminating specific diseases without strengthening health systems, for example, can result in failure to achieve even the desired health goals. (The Ebola crisis provides a case in point of the toll of such neglect).  Development strategy concerns how efforts of different kinds, which have effects on different time scales, should play a role in achieving the larger goals, in the presence of uncertainty. This question is best dealt with through democratic decision making, drawing on causal experience and practical judgment and making reference to shared values.

Why do we not make everything we do the subject of goal setting? Fetishizing goals can get in the way of living well, especially if our goals fail to encompass or anticipate important matters. For instance, as useful as measurement is, the notion that if something cannot be counted then it does not count can have serious costs. A regime of child-raising focused exclusively on measurable indicators would give insufficient attention to ideas such as that raising children well requires treating them with love and respect. This is an example of something that is difficult to measure but also happens to be a procedural value (though not all things that are of one kind are the other nor vice versa).  Inattention to procedural values is intrinsically undesirable but also very often gives rise to undesirable outcomes. In the collective context, the procedural value of democratic decision-making implies leaving goals and plans open to revision and is thus in tension with a target-centric perspective. Such openness to revision is also needed to produce desirable outcomes because the world and our knowledge of it change over time and because to implement policies effectively requires ongoing public perception that they are legitimate.

If the goals are meant as a mere rhetorical frame, then the adverse effects of a goal-centered concept of development, or of a poor specific choice of goals, can be safely ignored, and the whole SDG effort may be viewed as bombast. If, rather, the goals are intended to have a substantive impact, they must be better justified.

Global goals should be adopted only if we think that having goals does not undermine important procedural values, and if they will have epistemic, motivational or coordination roles that can lead to improvements in people’s lives. It is hard to imagine that the lengthy list of ‘targets’ and ‘indicators’ can satisfy these criteria. The higher-level goals, however, have some motivational force and may each individually possess a rationale.  Taken together, they provide something closer to a holistic vision.

A dual perspective is needed, in which a vision of a better world accompanies and is used to makes sense of specific general goals (such as poverty reduction or protecting the environment) while providing flexibility for, and guidance in, choosing differing emphases and priorities across and within them as values and circumstances require. This dual perspective is attractive for both empirical and evaluative reasons, even if it means a less directive approach to development.

If there must be development goals—which is far from obvious—then global quantitative targets should be de-emphasized or in some cases done away with altogether. Specific targets such as the reduction or elimination of particular causes of death or of poverty may retain their attractiveness but others will not. Global goals should be advanced through national plans that might not involve quantitative targets but that would specify strategies. Such national approaches should be the subject of discussion and review by the public within and outside countries, drawing on relevant expertise to improve their conception, execution and coordination. Such an approach would open more room for experimentation with innovative development strategies, and create a richer global public conversation on what development is, whom it should serve, how and why.


3 thoughts on “Global Goals: For What?

  1. Data driven:
    Agenda,
    Outlook;
    Market…
    Then one has to ask, who is “selecting” such supposedly aggregate data?
    In conventional développement models, research itself stems from an interest of the researcher in validating or not, a postulate… therein lies intentionality in the mix, predicating all outcomes: objectivity is a creation of the mind, not an objective fact!

    Like

  2. Several questions spring to mind (in addition to the ones raised in this incisive post). Who are these goals for? What does “adoption of these goals” mean in real terms? Shouldn’t countries have their own goals based on their priorities? While goals of poverty eradication. reducing hunger may be considered reasonably universal goals specific ones on health, livelihoods are so region and location specific. Of course, the poverty eradication goal is based on such a faulty premise (as we have all argued time and time again and Sanjay you more accurately and intensively than others) that this goal and others associated goals (such as health and nutrition) have no significance.

    The shortcomings in goal setting that the post has identified will lead to myopic strategy and actions required to achieve these goals as we have seen in the case of the MDG in India. E.g., malnutrition – to be achieved through energy bars / RTE therapeutic food aimed at specific nutrients rather than local, freshly cooked nutritious foods which are “whole” and result in longer term better health. In addition since it is location and culture specific it is more sustainable for communities to manage and generate livelihoods.

    Politically motivated efforts like these are such a colossal waste of time and resources….a travesty in the name of development.

    Like

Leave a comment